Question:
What is free will, and how does it work?
anonymous
2006-11-01 00:47:13 UTC
I'm looking for definitions of free will and descriptions of how it works. Could it be just an illusion? And would that be a bad thing?
Fourteen answers:
small
2006-11-01 02:57:52 UTC
Free will is indeed an illusion that feeds our ego and of course it is bad. Bad because we believe we have free will even though it is only an illusion.



There is no free will in this universe which runs on unexceptionable (universal) cause and effect chain.



Well, that's my personal belief not aided by any theory or treatise.
vinod s
2006-11-01 12:22:48 UTC
In every moment of your life You are free to decide what you would like to do.

There are limitations, for example right now you cannot fly, drive a ferari if you cannot afford it or ask and expect Angelina Jolie for a date.



Even when you are in Prison, you are free to either Read Write, Sing, Exercise, Sleep, Sit, Stand, Mediate etc., All these decisions are supposed to make up your destiny.



In other case a non living thing like a stone - has no free will as it cannot decide to avoid a hammer that you strike at it. It follows the Cause and Effect phenomena. You strike the stone with a Hammer, if it is weak enough it will break into pieces, if it is too hard you get an equal and opposite reaction!!!



Universe contains both the living and the non-living things so in the big scheme of things, free will and cause and effect phenomena are working every second to create its destiny.



Is the overall cause and effect pre-determined? If yes, then our free will is just an illusion.



If the overall cause and effect is not pre-determined and all the living things are sub-consciously trying to achieve something, that would be the purpose of life.



Thanks, you made my day. I have now put in simple words what I have been thinking for the past 20 years.



EnJoY
snocy
2006-11-01 09:41:05 UTC
There are so many different theories, it comes down to personal belief. Pick up any Personality Theory book and you will see just how varied the theories from the most renowned Psychologists are.



My theory, we have very little free will. We are bound by our basic drives, and very few components of our lives are not focused on those basic drives. We may have some free will as to how we meet those needs, but they must be met regularly.
anonymous
2006-11-01 18:22:52 UTC
Good, bad or indifferent you just excercised your free will by thinking on your own and going to your computer and typing out the question and then (your choice) to send to Yahoo Answers. Now you will excercise your free will with the freedom of choice by reading this. It is as simple as that. A voluntary deed without anyone controlling your brain or actions.
McDreamy
2006-11-01 10:44:06 UTC
Free will is the illusion of a sense of total control over our mind and action. Advances in science seems to indicate this free will is not so free after all, influenced by our internal molecular programming and by external influences. So in this context, free will is our ability to chart our destiny within the confine of those influences.
JF
2006-11-01 09:25:34 UTC
Good question - First off, you are not a doubter, Thomas, if you are still asking. I think that's great. God made us in His image. If He did not give us free will, we would be like slaves, forced to do things His way and that would not be a reciprocal loving relationship between Him and His children. He wants us to follow Him, but He wants us to be able to chose that for ourselves. That way we are following out of real love and submission. He leads His flock; He doean't drive them. If we are in His will, then we are denying the sin nature as much as possible and following Him and His will for us. Again, not because He made us, but because we chose it. And that, is because He loves us as our father, and we love Him as His children. He'll take care of us if we let Him by giving up our free will (which always gets us into trouble). Hope this answered your question. Keep asking. Jesus said, knock and the door will be a open to you, ask and you shall receive. Glad you are, JF (by the way - that's Jesus Freak)
Benelly
2006-11-01 08:57:12 UTC
Free will is your God given right and no one can take that away from you. It is not a bad thing. Everything we do, we are responsible for the outcome no matter if it is good or bad.
anonymous
2006-11-01 11:03:29 UTC
Man is born free and everywhere he is in chains - Voltaire. You have the free will to do anything that you are capable of but most people don't realise that they have such power.
offer your soup
2006-11-01 09:07:33 UTC
free will is the ability to choose and free well is limited to so many restrictions I am not talking about the human restrictions because not man can take your free will he could threaten you but you still can choose to respond in the way he wants or not even if he killed you he still could not let you do what he wants so your free will is always there for you but the restrictions are from the universe design like let us say the laws of energy you can not let energy disappear it will only transform from one shape to another regardless of what choices you want to make.

and as for saying is it a bad its only bad if you use it to get your selves things you don't want or to places you don't want to be in, if you get to what you want then its THEE good way of using your free will whether you choose heaven or hell or choose whets ever lasting for what to be finished.
anonymous
2006-11-01 08:53:19 UTC
read "Beyond and Dignity" by B. F. Skinner.

He is the Frankenstien of psychology.

It is all,about this question and it takes this whole book to answer it well.

Also SARTE is a good read on this.

" we are all doomed to be free"
anonymous
2006-11-01 09:08:37 UTC
You just used free will to ask this question.
clarence w
2006-11-01 10:01:10 UTC
the power of choice two doors gods way /your way would you lie for a million dollars have sex or murder no your consience knows its wrong but you must choose
anonymous
2006-11-01 08:54:54 UTC
Suicide is the supreme act of free will.
SINDY
2006-11-01 10:40:41 UTC
From answers.com:



Directory > Words > Dictionary

free will

n.



1. The ability or discretion to choose; free choice: chose to remain behind of my own free will.

2. The power of making free choices that are unconstrained by external circumstances or by an agency such as fate or divine will.



[Middle English fre wil, translation of Late Latin līberum arbitrium : Latin līberum, neuter of līber, free + Latin arbitrium, will.]



Wills

Free Legal Information & Resources on Estate Laws & Lawyers.

www.FindLaw.com

Free Will

Looking to find wills? Browse our wills directory.

WillsSearch.com

Back to Top Antonyms

Directory > Reference > Antonyms

free will

n



Definition: person's full intent and purpose

Antonyms: responsibility

Free Legal Forms Here

Need legal forms? Access 1000s of legal forms now. 100% Free.

FreeLawLibrary.us

Free Will

Questia. Faster, Easier Research Books, Journals and Articles Online

www.Questia.com

Back to Top Encyclopedia

Directory > Reference > Encyclopedia

free will, in philosophy, the doctrine that an individual, regardless of forces external to him, can and does choose at least some of his actions. The existence of free will is challenged by determinism. A denial of free will was implicit in Plato's argument that, because no one would deliberately choose a worse over a better course of action, people's decisions are determined by their understanding (or ignorance) of what constitutes the good. Aristotle disagreed; he distinguished between reason and desire, pointing out that people sometimes do what they desire even when they know it will harm themselves or others. Some Stoics sought to adapt the idea of free will to their rigorous form of determinism; Chrysippus emphasized that action could be produced by choice which itself had antecedent causes. In the Christian philosophical tradition a central question regarding freedom of the will was this: is virtue within the power of the individual or completely dependent on the power of God? St. Augustine, although he argued that God's foreknowledge of human actions (a consequence of his omniscience) did not cause them, did hold that God's omnipotent providence implied predestination: man was wholly dependent on divine grace. St. Thomas Aquinas maintained the freedom of man's will in spite of divine omnipotence, holding that God's omnipotence meant he could do all things possible or consistent with his goodness and reason, which did not include the predetermination of human will. William of Occam affirmed free will but claimed it impossible for any human to comprehend how it is compatible with God's foreknowledge and omniscience, which cannot be distinguished from his role as prime mover and original cause. Martin Luther and John Calvin both followed Augustine's doctrine of predestination, but later Protestant writers disputed their position. Advocates of free will have usually begun with the overwhelming testimony of common practice and common sense: people do believe they in some way determine their actions, and hold each other accountable for them. Therefore advocates of free will have argued that the human will, unlike inanimate things, can initiate its own activity.



Will & Testament Guide

Estate, Wills and Probates. Layman's Guide to Wills.

FuneralPlanning101.com

Giving Away Free Stuff

Free Samples From Top Brands! Simply Point, Select, and Receive.

www.1FreeStuffPlace.com

Back to Top Literature

Directory > Arts > Literature

free will



The ability to choose, think, and act voluntarily. For many philosophers, to believe in free will is to believe that human beings can be the authors of their own actions and to reject the idea that human actions are determined by external conditions or fate. (See determinism, fatalism, and predestination.)

Free Will

We've Found the Best 4 Sites About Free Will

Best7Sites.com

Download Free Will

Free Free Will track. Free Trial with no obligation. Aff.

www.real.com

Back to Top Quotes About

Directory > Words > Quotes About

Free Will



Quotes:



The most intellectual of men are moved quite as much by the circumstances which they are used to as by their own will. The active voluntary part of a man is very small, and if it were not economized by a sleepy kind of habit, its results would be null. - Walter Bagehot



The liberated man is not the one who is freed in his ideal reality, his inner truth, or his transparency; he is the man who changes spaces, who circulates, who changes sex, clothes, and habits according to fashion, rather than morality, and who changes opinions not as his conscience dictates but in response to opinion polls. - Jean Baudrillard



Whereas the Greeks gave to will the boundaries of reason, we have come to put the will's impulse in the very center of reason, which has, as a result, become deadly. - Albert Camus



The will is never free -- it is always attached to an object, a purpose. It is simply the engine in the car -- it can't steer. - Joyce Cary



Do what thou wilt shall be the whole of the law. - Aleister Crowley



There are no galley-slaves in the royal vessel of divine love -- every man works his oar voluntarily! - St. Francis De Sales



A man may be a pessimistic determinist before lunch and an optimistic believer in the will's freedom after it. - Aldous Huxley



There are no galley-slaves in the royal vessel of divine love -- every man works his oar voluntarily! - St. Francis De Sales



Do what thou wilt shall be the whole of the law. - Aleister Crowley



The will is never free -- it is always attached to an object, a purpose. It is simply the engine in the car -- it can't steer. - Joyce Cary



Whereas the Greeks gave to will the boundaries of reason, we have come to put the will's impulse in the very center of reason, which has, as a result, become deadly. - Albert Camus



The liberated man is not the one who is freed in his ideal reality, his inner truth, or his transparency; he is the man who changes spaces, who circulates, who changes sex, clothes, and habits according to fashion, rather than morality, and who changes opinions not as his conscience dictates but in response to opinion polls. - Jean Baudrillard



The most intellectual of men are moved quite as much by the circumstances which they are used to as by their own will. The active voluntary part of a man is very small, and if it were not economized by a sleepy kind of habit, its results would be null. - Walter Bagehot



For more famous quotes about Free Will, visit Quotations Book.

100% Free Samples & Stuff

Totally Free Samples. No scams. The most Free Stuff online!

Free-For-U.com/Free_Stuff

Legal Forms - Living Will

Contracts, form letters, more Download and use immediately.

www.uslegalforms.com

Back to Top WordNet

Directory > Words > WordNet

Note: click on a word meaning below to see its connections and related words.



The noun free will has one meaning:



Meaning #1: the power of making free choices unconstrained by external agencies

Synonym: discretion

Make a Will online $7.50

Not just a form - we guide you all the way. Prints out ready to sign.

www.MakeYourWill.com

Get Free Stuff Online

Find Tons of Free Stuff After All, Its Better Free

www.itsbetterfree.com

Back to Top Wikipedia

Directory > Reference > Wikipedia

free will



This article covers the non-theological aspects of free will. For the theological aspects, see Free will in theology. For the music label, see Free-Will (label).



The problem of free will is the problem of whether human beings exercise control over their own actions and decisions. Addressing this problem requires understanding the relation between freedom and causation, and determining whether or not the laws of nature are causally deterministic. The various positions taken on the problem therefore differ on whether all events are determined or not—determinism versus indeterminism—and differ on whether freedom can co-exist with determinism or not—compatibilism versus incompatibilism. So, for instance, hard determinists argue that the universe is deterministic, and that this makes free will impossible.



The principle of free will has religious, ethical, and scientific implications. For example, in the religious realm, free will may imply that an omnipotent divinity does not assert its power over individual will and choices. In ethics, it may imply that individuals can be held morally accountable for their actions. In psychology, it may imply that the mind controls some of the actions of the body. In the scientific realm, it may imply that the actions of the body, including the brain, are not wholly determined by physical causality. The question of free will has been a central issue since the beginning of philosophical thought.



Free will in philosophy

A simplified taxonomy of the possible philosophical positions regarding free will.

Enlarge

A simplified taxonomy of the possible philosophical positions regarding free will.



The basic philosophical positions on the problem of free will can be divided in accordance with the answers they provide to two questions: 1) Is determinism true? and 2) Does free will exist? Determinism is roughly defined as the view that all current and future events are necessitated by past events combined with the laws of nature. Neither determinism nor its opposite, non-determinism, are positions in the debate about free will.[1]



Compatibilism is the view that accepts both the existence of free will and the truth of determinism, claiming that they are compatible with each other. Incompatibilism is the view that there is no way to reconcile a belief in a deterministic universe with a belief in free will.[2] Hard determinism is the version of incompatibilism that accepts the truth of determinism and rejects the idea that humans have any free will.[3] Metaphysical libertarianism agrees with hard determinism only in rejecting compatibilism. Since libertarians accept the existence of free will, they must reject determinism and argue for some version of indeterminism that is compatible with freedom.[4]



Determinism



Main article: Determinism



Determinism is a broad term which encompasses a variety of meanings. Corresponding to each of these different usages, there arises a different problem of free will.[5]



Causal (or nomological) determinism is the thesis that future events are necessitated by past and present events combined with the laws of nature. Such determinism is sometimes illustrated by the thought experiment of Laplace's demon. Imagine an entity that knows all facts about the past and the present, and knows all natural laws that govern the universe. Such an entity is able to use this knowledge to foresee the future, down to the smallest detail.[6]



Logical determinism is the notion that all propositions, whether about the past, present or future, are either true or false. The problem of free will, in this context, is the problem of how choices can be free, given that what one does in the future is already determined as true or false in the present.[5]



Theological determinism is the thesis that there is a God who determines all that humans will do, either by knowing their actions in advance, via some form of omniscience[7] or by decreeing their actions in advance.[8] The problem of free will, in this context, is the problem of how our actions can be free, if there is a being who has determined them for us ahead of time.



Biological determinism is the idea that all behavior, belief, and desire are fixed by our genetic endowment. There are other theses on determinism, including cultural determinism and psychological determinism.[5] In this article, only causal determinism is discussed.



Compatibilism

Thomas Hobbes was a classical compatibilist.

Enlarge

Thomas Hobbes was a classical compatibilist.



Compatibilists maintain that determinism is compatible with free will. A common strategy employed by "classical compatibilists", such as Thomas Hobbes, is to claim that a person acts freely only when the person willed the act and the person could have done otherwise, if the person had decided to.[9] In articulating this crucial proviso, David Hume writes, "this hypothetical liberty is universally allowed to belong to every one who is not a prisoner and in chains".[10] To illustrate their position, compatibilists point to clear-cut cases of someone's free will being denied, through rape, murder, theft, or other forms of constraint. In these cases, free will is lacking not because the past is causally determining the future, but because the aggressor is overriding the victim's desires and preferences about his own actions. The aggressor is coercing the victim and, according to compatibilists, this is what overrides free will. Thus, they argue that determinism does not matter; what matters is that individuals' choices are the results of their own desires and preferences, and are not overridden by some external (or internal) force.[9][10] To be a compatibilist, one need not endorse any particular conception of free will, but only deny that determinism is at odds with free will.[1]



William James's views were ambivalent. While he believed in free will on "ethical grounds," he did not believe that there was evidence for it on scientific grounds. Moreover, he did not accept incompatibilism as formulated above; he did not believe that the indeterminism of human actions was a prerequisite of moral responsibility. In his work Pragmatism, he wrote that "instinct and utility between them can safely be trusted to carry on the social business of punishment and praise" regardless of metaphysical theories.[11] He did believe that indeterminism is important as a "doctrine of relief"—it allows for the view that, although the world may be in many respects a bad place, it may through individuals' actions become a better one. Determinism, he argued, undermines meliorism—the idea that progress is a real concept leading to improvement in the world.[11]



"Modern compatibilists", such as Harry Frankfurt and Daniel Dennett, argue that there are cases where a coerced agent's choices are still free because such coercion coincides with the agent's personal intentions and desires.[12][13] Frankfurt, in particular, argues for a version of compatibilism called the "hierarchical mesh". The idea is that an individual can have conflicting desires at a first-order level and also have a desire about the various first-order desires (a second-order desire) to the effect that one of the desires prevail over the others. A person's will is to be identified with her effective first-order desire, i.e., the one that she acts on. So, for example, there are "wanton addicts", "unwilling addicts" and "willing addicts." All three groups may have the conflicting first-order desires to want to take the drug to which they are addicted and to not want to take it. The first group has no second-order desire not to take the drug. The second group has a second-order desire not to take the drug, while the third group has a second-order desire to take it. According to Frankfurt, the members of the first group are to be considered devoid of will and therefore no longer persons. The members of the second group freely desire not to take the drug, but their will is overcome by the addiction. Finally, the members of the third group willingly take the drug to which they are addicted. Frankfurt's theory can ramify to any number of levels. Critics of the theory point out that there is no certainty that conflicts will not arise even at the higher-order levels of desire and preference.[14] Others argue that Frankfurt offers no adequate explanation of how the various levels in the hierarchy mesh together.[15]



In Elbow Room, Dennett presents an argument for a compatibilist theory of free will, which he further elaborated in the book Freedom Evolves.[16] The basic reasoning is that, if one excludes God, an infinitely powerful demon, and other such possibilities, then because of chaos and quantum randomness, the future is ill-defined for all finite beings. The only well-defined things are "expectations". The ability to do "otherwise" only makes sense when dealing with these expectations, and not with some unknown and unknowable future. Since individuals have the ability to act differently from what anyone expects, free will can exist.[16] Incompatibilists claim the problem with this idea is that we may be mere "automata responding in predictable ways to stimuli in our environment". Therefore, all of our actions are controlled by forces outside ourselves, or by random chance.[17] More sophisticated analyses of compatibilist free will have been offered, as have other critiques.[1]



Incompatibilism

Baron d'Holbach was a hard determinist

Enlarge

Baron d'Holbach was a hard determinist



"Hard determinists", such as d'Holbach, are those incompatibilists who accept determinism and reject free will. "Metaphysical libertarians", such as Thomas Reid, Peter van Inwagen, and Robert Kane, are those incompatibilists who accept free will and deny determinism, holding the view that some form of indeterminism is true.[18]



One of the traditional arguments for incompatibilism is based on an "intuition pump". The idea is simply that if man is determined in his choices of actions, then he must be like other mechanical things that are determined in their behavior. That is, if man's behavior is causally determined, then he is nothing more sophisticated than a wind-up toy, a billiard ball, a puppet, or a robot. Since these things have no free will, then man must have no free will, if determinism is true.[19][18] This argument has been rejected by compatibilists such as Daniel Dennett on the grounds that, even if humans have something in common with these things, it does not follow that there are no important differences.[13]



Another argument for incompatibilism is that of the "causal chain." Most incompatibilists reject the idea that freedom of action consists simply in "voluntary" behavior. They insist, rather, that free will means that man must be the "ultimate" or "originating" cause of his actions. He must be a causa sui, in the traditional phrase. To be responsible for one's choices is to be the first cause of those choices, where first cause means that there is no antecedent cause of that cause. The argument, then, is that if man has free will, then man is the ultimate cause of his actions. If determinism is true, then all of man's choices are caused by events and facts outside his control. So, if everything man does is caused by events and facts outside his control, then he cannot be the ultimate cause of his actions. Therefore, he cannot have free will.[20][21][22] This argument has also been challenged by various compatibilist philosophers.[23][24]



A third argument for incompatibilism was formulated by Carl Ginet in the 1960s and has received much attention in the modern literature. The simplified argument runs along these lines: if determinism is true, then we have no control over the events of the past that determined our present state and no control over the laws of nature. Since we can have no control over these matters, we also can have no control over the consequences of them. Since our present choices and acts, under determinism, are the necessary consequences of the past and the laws of nature, then we have no control over them and, hence, no free will. This is called the consequence argument.[25][26]



The difficulty of this argument for compatibilists lies in the fact that it entails the impossibility that one could have chosen other than one has. For example, if Jane is a compatibilist and she has just sat down on the sofa, then she is committed to the claim that she could have remained standing, if she had so desired. But it follows from the consequence argument that, if Jane had remained standing, she would have either generated a contradiction, violated the laws of nature or changed the past. Hence, compatibilists are committed to the existence of "incredible abilities", according to Ginet and van Inwagen. One response to this argument is that it equivocates on the notions of abilities and necessities.[26] David Lewis suggests that compatibilists are only committed to the ability to do something otherwise if different circumstances had actually obtained in the past.[27]



Other views

Much of Arthur Schopenhauer's writing is focused on the notion of will and its relation to freedom.

Enlarge

Much of Arthur Schopenhauer's writing is focused on the notion of will and its relation to freedom.



Some philosophers' views are difficult to categorize as either compatibilist or incompatibilist, hard determinist or libertarian. John Locke, for example, denied that the phrase "free will" made any sense. He also took the view that the truth of determinism was irrelevant. He believed that the defining feature of voluntary behavior was that individuals have the ability to postpone a decision long enough to reflect or deliberate upon the consequences of a choice: "...the will in truth, signifies nothing but a power, or ability, to prefer or choose".[28]



Arthur Schopenhauer put the puzzle of free will and moral responsiblity in these terms:



Everyone believes himself a priori to be perfectly free, even in his individual actions, and thinks that at every moment he can commence another manner of life... . But a posteriori, through experience, he finds to his astonishment that he is not free, but subjected to necessity, that in spite of all his resolutions and reflections he does not change his conduct, and that from the beginning of his life to the end of it, he must carry out the very character which he himself condemns...."[29]



In his On the Freedom of the Will, Schopenhauer stated, "You can do what you will, but in any given moment of your life you can will only one definite thing and absolutely nothing other than that one thing." [30]



The contemporary philosopher Galen Strawson agrees with Locke that the truth or falsity of determinism is irrelevant to the problem.[4] He argues that the notion of free will leads to an infinite regress and is therefore senseless. According to Strawson, if one is responsible for what one does in a given situation, then one must be responsible for the way one is in certain mental respects. But it is impossible for one to be responsible for the way one is in any respect. This is because in order to be responsible for the way one is in some situation "S", one must have been responsible for the way one was at "S-1". In order to be responsible for the way one was at "S-1", one must have been responsible for the way one was at "S-2", and so on. At some point in the chain, there must have been an act of origination of a new causal chain. But this is impossible. Man cannot create himself or his mental states ex nihilo. This argument entails that free will itself is absurd, but not that it is incompatible with determinism. Strawson calls his own view "pessimism".[4]



Ted Honderich holds the view that "determinism is true, compatibilism and incompatibilism are both false" and the real problem lies elsewhere. Honderich maintains that determinism is true because quantum phenomena are not events or things that can be located in space and time, but are abstract entities. Further, even if they were micro-level events, they do not seem to have any relevance to how the world is at the macroscopic level. He maintains that incompatibilism is false because, even if determinism is true, incompatibilists have not, and cannot, provide an adequate account of origination. He rejects compatibilism because it, like incompatibilism, assumes a single, fundamental notion of freedom. There are really two notions of freedom: voluntary action and origination. Both notions are needed in order to explain freedom of will and responsibility. Both determinism and indeterminism are threats to such freedom. To abandon these notions of freedom would be to abandon moral responsibility. On the one side, we have our intuitions; on the other, the scientific facts. The "new" problem is how to resolve this conflict.[31]



Moral responsibility

The defense of Nathan Leopold (left) and Richard Loeb (center) questioned the idea of moral responsibility.

The defense of Nathan Leopold (left) and Richard Loeb (center) questioned the idea of moral responsibility.



Society generally holds people responsible for their actions, and will say that they deserve praise or blame for what they do. However, many believe that moral responsibility requires free will. Thus, another important issue is whether individuals are ever morally responsible for their actions—and, if so, in what sense.



Incompatibilists tend to think that determinism is at odds with moral responsibility. It seems impossible that one can hold someone responsible for an action that could be predicted from the beginning of time. Hard determinists say "So much the worse for free will!" and discard the concept.[32] Clarence Darrow, the famous defense attorney, pleaded the innocence of his clients, Leopold and Loeb, by invoking such a notion of hard determinism.[33] During his summation, he declared:



What has this boy to do with it? He was not his own father; he was not his own mother; he was not his own grandparents. All of this was handed to him. He did not surround himself with governesses and wealth. He did not make himself. And yet he is to be compelled to pay.[33]



Conversely, libertarians say "So much the worse for determinism!"[32] Daniel Dennett asks why anyone would care about whether someone had the property of responsibility and speculates that the idea of moral responsibility may be "a purely metaphysical hankering".[13] Jean-Paul Sartre argues that people sometimes avoid incrimination and responsibility by hiding behind determinism: "... we are always ready to take refuge in a belief in determinism if this freedom weighs upon us or if we need an excuse".[34]



The issue of moral responsibility is at the heart of the dispute between hard determinists and compatibilists. Hard determinists are forced to accept that individuals often have "free will" in the compatibilist sense, but they deny that this sense of free will can ground moral responsibility. The fact that an agent's choices are unforced, hard determinists claim, does not change the fact that determinism robs the agent of responsibility.



Compatibilists argue, on the contrary, that determinism is a prerequisite for moral responsibility. Society cannot hold someone responsible unless his actions were determined by something. This argument can be traced back to Hume. If indeterminism is true, then those events that are not determined are random. It is doubtful that one can praise or blame someone for performing an action generated spontaneously by his nervous system. Instead, one needs to show how the action stemmed from the person's desires and preferences—the person's character—before one can hold the person morally responsible.[10] Libertarians may reply that undetermined actions are not random at all, and that they result from a substantive will whose decisions are undetermined. This argument is considered unsatisfactory by compatibilists, for it just pushes the problem back a step. It also seems to involve some mysterious metaphysics, as well as the concept of ex nihilo nihil fit. Libertarians have responded by trying to clarify how undetermined will could be tied to robust agency.[35]



St. Paul, in his Epistle to the Romans addresses the question of moral responsibility as follows: "Hath not the potter power over the clay, of the same lump to make one vessel unto honour, and another unto dishonour?"[36] In this view, individuals can still be dishonoured for their acts even though those acts were ultimately completely determined by God.



A similar view has it that individual moral culpability lies in individual character. That is, a person with the character of a murderer has no choice other than to murder, but can still be punished because it is right to punish those of bad character. How one's character was determined is irrelevant from this perspective. Hence, Robert Cummins and others argue that people should not be judged for their individual actions, but rather for how those actions "reflect on their character". If character (however defined) is the dominant causal factor in determining one's choices, and one's choices are morally wrong, then one should be held accountable for those choices, regardless of genes and other such factors.[37][38]



One exception to the assumption that moral culpability lies in either individual character or freely willed acts is in cases where the insanity defense—or its corollary, diminished responsibility—can be used to argue that the guilty deed was not the product of a guilty mind.[39] In such cases, the legal systems of most Western societies assume that the person is in some way not at fault, because his actions were a consequence of abnormal brain function.



Joshua Greene and Jonathan Cohen, researchers in the emerging field of neuroethics, argue, on the basis of such cases, that our current notion of moral responsibility is founded on libertarian (and dualist) intuitions.[40] They argue that cognitive neuroscience research is undermining these intuitions by showing that the brain is responsible for our actions, not only in cases of florid psychosis, but even in less obvious situations. For example, damage to the frontal lobe reduces the ability to weigh uncertain risks and make prudent decisions, and therefore leads to an increased likelihood that someone will commit a violent crime.[41] This is true not only of patients with damage to the frontal lobe due to accident or stroke, but also of adolescents, who show reduced frontal lobe activity compared to adults,[42] and even of children who are chronically neglected or mistreated.[43] In each case, the guilty party can be said to have less responsibility for his actions.[40] Greene and Cohen predict that, as such examples become more common and well known, jurors’ interpretations of free will and moral responsibility will move away from the intuitive libertarian notion which currently underpins them.



Greene and Cohen also argue that the legal system does not require this libertarian interpretation. Only retributive notions of justice, in which the goal of the legal system is to punish people for misdeeds, require the libertarian intuition. Consequentialist approaches to justice, which are aimed at promoting future welfare rather than meting out just deserts, can survive even a hard determinist interpretation of free will. The legal system and notions of justice can thus be maintained even in the face of emerging neuroscientific evidence undermining libertarian intuitions of free will.



Science and free will



Physics and free will



Since the beginnings of science, people have attempted to solve the problem of free will using scientific methods. Early scientific thought often pictured the universe as deterministic,[44] and some thinkers believed that it was simply a matter of gathering sufficient information to be able to predict future events with perfect accuracy. This vision entailed that free will must be an illusion.



Modern science, on the other hand, is a mixture of deterministic and stochastic theories.[45] The possibility that the universe at the macroscopic level may be governed by indeterministic laws, as it is at the quantum level, has revived interest in free will among physicists. Quantum mechanics predicts events only in terms of probabilities, casting doubt on whether the universe is deterministic at all. Some scientific determinists, following Albert Einstein, believe in so-called "hidden variable theories" that entail that beneath the probabilities of quantum mechanics there are fixed variables (see the EPR paradox).[46] These theories were cast into doubt by the discovery of Bell's Inequality.[46] Robert Kane has capitalized on the success of quantum mechanics and chaos theory in order to defend incompatibilist freedom in his The Significance of Free Will and other writing.[47]



In a 1928 speech to the German League for Human Rights, Einstein summarized his dismissal of free will in these terms:



I don’t believe in the freedom of the will. Schopenhauer’s saying, that a human can very well do what he wants, but can not will what he wants, accompanies me in all of life’s circumstances and reconciles me with the actions of humans, even when they are truly distressing. This knowledge of the non-freedom of the will protects me from losing my good humor and taking much too seriously myself and my fellow humans as acting and judging individuals.[48]



Genetics and free will



Like physicists, biologists have frequently addressed questions related to free will. One of the most heated debates in biology is that of "nature versus nurture", concerning the relative importance of genetics and biology as compared to culture and environment in human behavior.[49] The view of most researchers is that many human behaviors can be explained in terms of humans' brains, genes, and evolutionary histories.[50][51][52] This raises the fear that such attribution makes it impossible to hold others responsible for their actions. Steven Pinker's view is that fear of determinism in the context of "genetics" and "evolution" is a mistake, that it is "a confusion of explanation with exculpation". Responsibility doesn't require behavior to be uncaused, as long as behaviour responds to praise and blame.[53] Moreover, it is not certain that environmental determination is any less threatening to free will than genetic determination.[54]



Neuroscience and free will

Typical recording of the readiness potential. Libet investigated whether this neural activity corresponded to the "felt intention" (or will) to move of experimental subjects.

Enlarge

Typical recording of the readiness potential. Libet investigated whether this neural activity corresponded to the "felt intention" (or will) to move of experimental subjects.



It has become possible to study the living brain, and researchers can now watch the brain's decision-making "machinery" at work. A seminal experiment in this field was conducted by Benjamin Libet in the 1980s, in which he asked each subject to choose a random moment to flick her wrist while he measured the associated activity in her brain (in particular, the build-up of electrical signal called the readiness potential). Although it was well known that the readiness potential preceded the physical action, Libet asked whether the readiness potential corresponded to the felt intention to move. To determine when the subject felt the intention to move, he asked her to watch the second hand of a clock and report its position when she felt that she had the conscious will to move.[55]



Libet found that the unconscious brain activity leading up to the conscious decision by the subject to flick his or her wrist began approximately half a second before the subject consciously felt that she had decided to move.[55][56] Libet's findings suggest that decisions made by a subject are first being made on a subconscious level and only afterward being translated into a "conscious decision", and that the subject's belief that it occurred at the behest of her will was only due to her retrospective perspective on the event. The interpretation of these findings has been criticized by Daniel Dennett, who argues that people will have to shift their attention from their intention to the clock, and that this introduces temporal mismatches between the felt experience of will and the perceived position of the clock hand.[57][58] Consistent with this argument, subsequent studies have shown that the exact numerical value varies depending on attention.[59][60] Despite the differences in the exact numerical value, however, the main finding has held.[61]



In a variation of this task, Haggard and Eimer asked subjects to decide not only when to move their hands, but also to decide which hand to move. In this case, the felt intention correlated much more closely with the "lateralized readiness potential" (LRP), an EEG component which measures the difference between left and right hemisphere brain activity. Haggard and Eimer argue that the feeling of conscious will therefore must follow the decision of which hand to move, since the LRP reflects the decision to lift a particular hand.[59]



Related experiments showed that neurostimulation could affect which hands people move, even though the experience of free will was intact. Ammon and Gandevia found that it was possible to influence which hand people move by stimulating frontal regions that are involved in movement planning using transcranial magnetic stimulation in either the left or right hemisphere of the brain.[62] Right-handed people would normally choose to move their right hand 60% of the time, but when the right hemisphere was stimulated they would instead choose their left hand 80% of the time (recall that the right hemisphere of the brain is responsible for the left side of the body, and the left hemisphere for the right). Despite the external influence on their decision-making, the subjects continued to report that they believed their choice of hand had been made freely. In a follow-up experiment, Alvaro Pascual-Leone and colleagues found similar results, but also noted that the transcranial magnetic stimulation must occur within 200 milliseconds, consistent with the time-course derived from the Libet experiments.[63]



Despite these findings, Libet himself does not interpret his experiment as evidence of the inefficacy of conscious free will—he points out that although the tendency to press a button may be building up for 500 milliseconds, the conscious will retains a right to veto that action in the last few milliseconds.[64] According to this model, unconscious impulses to perform a volitional act are open to suppression by the conscious efforts of the subject (sometimes referred to as "free won't"). A comparison is made with a golfer, who may swing a club several times before striking the ball. The action simply gets a rubber stamp of approval at the last millisecond.



Neurology and psychiatry



There are several brain-related conditions in which an individual's actions are not felt to be entirely under his or her control. Although the existence of such conditions does not directly refute the existence of free will, the study of such conditions, like the neuroscientific studies above, is valuable in developing models of how the brain may construct our experience of free will.



For example, people with Tourette syndrome and related tic disorders make involuntary movements and utterances, called tics, despite the fact that they would prefer not to do so when it is socially inappropriate. Tics are described as semi-voluntary or "unvoluntary",[65] because they are not strictly involuntary: they may be experienced as a voluntary response to an unwanted, premonitory urge. Tics are experienced as irresistible and must eventually be expressed.[65] People with Tourette syndrome are sometimes able to suppress their tics to some extent for limited periods, but doing so often results in an explosion of tics afterward. The control which can be exerted (from seconds to hours at a time) may merely postpone and exacerbate the ultimate expression of the tic.[66]



In alien hand syndrome, the afflicted individual's limb will produce meaningful behaviours without the intention of the subject. The clinical definition requires "feeling that one limb is foreign or has a will of its own, together with observable involuntary motor activity" (emphasis in original).[67] This syndrome is often a result of damage to the corpus callosum, either when it is severed to treat intractable epilepsy or due to a stroke. The standard neurological explanation is that the felt will reported by the speaking left hemisphere does not correspond with the actions performed by the non-speaking right hemisphere, thus suggesting that the two hemispheres may have independent senses of will. [68][69]



Similarly, one of the most important ("first rank") diagnostic symptoms of schizophrenia is the delusion of being controlled by an external force.[70] People with schizophrenia will sometimes report that, although they are acting in the world, they did not initiate, or will, the particular actions they performed. This is sometimes likened to being a robot controlled by someone else. Although the neural mechanisms of schizophrenia are not yet clear, one influential hypothesis is that there is a breakdown in brain systems that compare motor commands with the feedback received from the body (known as proprioception), leading to attendant hallucinations and delusions of control.[71]



Determinism and emergent behaviour



Main article: Emergence



In generative philosophy of cognitive sciences and evolutionary psychology, free will is assumed not to exist.[72][73] However, an illusion of free will is created, within this theoretical context, due to the generation of infinite or computationally complex behaviour from the interaction of a finite set of rules and parameters. Thus, the unpredictability of the emerging behaviour from deterministic processes leads to a perception of free will, even though free will as an ontological entity is assumed not to exist. [72][73] In this picture, even if the behavior could be computed ahead of time, no way of doing so will be simpler than just observing the outcome of the brain's own computations. [74]



As an illustration, some strategy board games have rigorous rules in which no information (such as cards' face values) is hidden from either player and no random events (such as dice-rolling) occur in the game. Nevertheless, strategy games like chess and especially Go, with its simple deterministic rules, can have an extremely large number of unpredictable moves. By analogy, "emergentists" suggest that the experience of free will emerges from the interaction of finite rules and deterministic parameters that generate infinite and unpredictable behaviour. Yet, if all these events were accounted for, and there were a known way to evaluate these events, the seemingly unpredictable behavior would become predictable.[72][73]



Cellular automata and the generative sciences model emergent processes of social behavior on this philosophy, showing the experience of free will to be a gift of ignorance or a product of incomplete information.[72]



In Hindu philosophy

Swami Vivekananda: "there cannot be any such thing as free-will; the very words are a contradiction".

Enlarge

Swami Vivekananda: "there cannot be any such thing as free-will; the very words are a contradiction".



The six orthodox (astika) schools of thought in Hindu philosophy do not agree with each other entirely on the question of free will. For the Samkhya, for instance, matter is without any freedom, and soul lacks any ability to control the unfolding of matter. The only real freedom (kaivalya) consists in realizing the ultimate separateness of matter and self. For the Yoga school, only Ishvara is truly free, and its freedom is also distinct from all feelings, thoughts, actions, or wills, and is thus not at all a freedom of will. The metaphysics of the Nyaya and Vaisheshika schools strongly suggest a belief in determinism, but do not seem to make explicit claims about determinism or free will.[75]



A quotation from Swami Vivekananda, a Vedantist, offers a good example of the worry about free will in the Hindu tradition.



Therefore we see at once that there cannot be any such thing as free-will; the very words are a contradiction, because will is what we know, and everything that we know is within our universe, and everything within our universe is moulded by conditions of time, space and causality. ... To acquire freedom we have to get beyond the limitations of this universe; it cannot be found here.[76]



On the other hand, Mimamsa, Vedanta, and the more theistic versions of Hinduism such as Shaivism and Vaishnavism, have often emphasized the importance of free will. The doctrine of Karma in Hinduism requires both that we pay for our actions in the past, and that our actions in the present be free enough to allow us to deserve the future reward or punishment that we will receive for our present actions. The Advaitin philosopher Chandrashekhara Bharati Swaminah puts it this way:



Fate is past karma, free-will is present karma. Both are really one, that is, karma, though they may differ in the matter of time. There can be no conflict when they are really one.



Fate, as I told you, is the resultant of the past exercise of your free-will. By exercising your free-will in the past, you brought on the resultant fate. By exercising your free-will in the present, I want you to wipe out your past record if it hurts you, or to add to it if you find it enjoyable. In any case, whether for acquiring more happiness or for reducing misery, you have to exercise your free-will in the present.[77]



In Buddhist philosophy



Buddhism accepts both freedom and determinism (or something similar to it), but rejects the idea of an agent, and thus the idea that freedom is a free will belonging to an agent.[78]



The Buddha wrote, "There is free action, there is retribution, but I see no agent that passes out from one set of momentary elements into another one, except the [connection] of those elements."[78]



Buddhism takes something like causal determinism as one of its central doctrines. The doctrine is called pratitya-samutpada in Sanskrit, and is often translated as "dependent co-origination", and is part of the theory of Karma in Buddhism. However, denials of freedom are taken to be in danger of undermining the efforts of Buddhists to make moral progress. Pubbekatahetuvada, the belief that all happiness and suffering arise from previous actions, is considered a wrong view in Theravada, for instance.



Because Buddhists also reject agenthood, the traditional compatibilist strategies are closed to them as well. Instead, the Buddhist philosophical strategy is to examine the metaphysics of causality. Ancient India had active fights about the nature of causality with Jains, Nyayists, Samkhyists, Carvakans, and Buddhists all taking slightly different lines. In many ways, the Buddhist position is closer to a theory of "conditionality" than a theory of "causality", especially as it is expounded by Nagarjuna in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā.[78]



A contemporary American monk, Thanissaro Bhikkhu, puts it this way:



The Buddha's teachings on karma are interesting because it's a combination of causality and free-will. If things were totally caused there would be no way you could develop a skill - your actions would be totally predetermined. If there was no causality at all skills would be useless because things would be constantly changing without any kind of rhyme or reason to them. But it's because there is an element of causality and because there is this element of free-will you can develop skills in life."[79]



In theology



Main article: Free will in theology



The theological doctrine of divine foreknowledge is often alleged to be in conflict with free will. After all, if God knows exactly what will happen, right down to every choice one makes, the status of choices as free is called into question. If God had timelessly true knowledge about one's choices, this would seem to constrain one's freedom.[80] This problem is related to the Aristotelian problem of the sea battle: tomorrow there will or will not be a sea battle. If there will be one, then it seems that it was true yesterday that there would be one. Then it would be necessary that the sea battle will occur. If there won't be one, then by similar reasoning, it is necessary that it won't occur.[81] This means that the future, whatever it is, is completely fixed by past truths—true propositions about the future.



However, some philosophers follow William of Ockham in holding that necessity and possibility are defined with respect to a given point in time and a given matrix of empirical circumstances, and so something that is merely possible from the perspective of one observer may be necessary from the perspective of an omniscient.[82] Some philosophers follow Philo of Alexandria in holding that free will is a feature of a human's soul, and thus that animals lack free will.[83] Jewish philosophy stresses that free will is a product of the intrinsic human soul, using the word neshama (from the Hebrew root nshm or נשמ meaning "breath"). In Islam the theological issue is not usually how to reconcile free will with God's foreknowledge, but with God's jabr, or divine commanding power. al-Ash'ari developed an "acquisition" or "dual-agency" form of compatibilism, in which human free will and divine jabr were both asserted, and which became a cornerstone of the dominant Ash'ari position.[84] The philosopher Søren Kierkegaard claimed that divine omnipotence cannot be separated from divine goodness.[85] As a truly omnipotent and good being, God could create beings with true freedom over God. Furthermore, God would voluntarily do so because "the greatest good ... which can be done for a being, greater than anything else that one can do for it, is to be truly free."[86] Alvin Plantinga's "free will defense" is a contemporary expansion of this theme, adding how God, free will, and evil are consistent.[87]


This content was originally posted on Y! Answers, a Q&A website that shut down in 2021.
Loading...